归一云思
主页网络文摘杂文
文章内容页

Habermas and Hermeneutics:From Verstehen to Lebenswelt

  • 作者: 文艺理论研究
  • 来源: 归一文学
  • 发表于2023-11-09
  • 热度18742
  • Richard Wolin

      Abstract:Throughout his career, Habermas sought to remain faithful to the idea of a non-dogmatic and reflexive Marxism-Marxism as “critique.”Although Habermas never adopted the framework of social phenomenology per se, by the same token, his reception of the later Husserl’s notion of the lifeworld would play a central methodological role in his later work, enabling him to parry the well-entrenched scientistic biases of philosophy and social science.In “Knowledge and Human Interests”(1965), his inaugural lecture at University of Frankfurt, Habermas embraced Husserl’s critique of modern science’s misguided “mathematicization of nature.”Yet his systematic employment of Husserl would not occur until Theory of Communicative Action (1981).There, the notion of the “Lifeworld”(Lebenswelt)as an inexhaustible repository of non-thetic, implicit meanings signifies a reservoir of semantic resistance vis--vis the predatory subsystems of “money”and “power”(Geld und Macht)that, under late capitalism, increasingly assume hegemony.Habermas coined the phrase, the “colonization of the lifeworld,”to describe the process whereby informal spheres of human interaction are increasingly subjected to regulation and control by superordinate economic and bureaucratic structures.For Habermas, the discourse of social phenomenology, as it derived from the later Husserl, ultimately supplanted the role that “hermeneutics”had formerly played in his work—that is, as a methodological alternative to the objectivating approach that the social sciences.For Habermas, the attempt to remedy philosophy’s positivistic self-misunderstanding was more than an abstract, theoretical concern.At stake was the growing “scientific-technical organization of the lifeworld,”whose expansion had begun to threaten to the normative self-understanding of the West, which, in Habermas’s view, revolved around the mutually complementary ideals of individual autonomy and democratic self-determination.In this respect, Habermas’constructive encounter with the later Husserl was wholly consistent with his overall project of developing a “Critical Theory with a practical intent.”

      Keywords:Habermas; Critical Theory; HermeneuticsHusserl came to social phenomenology relatively late in life, with his 1936 manuscript on theCrisis

      of

      the

      European

      Sciences

      and

      Transcendental

      Phenomenology.Two decades laterits reception helped to inspire the emergence ofphenomenological

      Marxism.In Central Europe, this paradigmstood as a reflexive alternative to official Marxism qua “diamat”(dialectical materialism)which, in the lands of “really existing socialism,”had congealed into a dogmatic and repressive “science of legitimation.”Phenomenological Marxism’s leading representatives were Sartre, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Karel Kosik, Tran Duc Thao, and Enzo Paci.In the Czech context, one might go so far as to say that, given Kosik’sprominence, it played an important role in the Renaissance of Marxist humanism that culminated in the notion of “Socialism with a Human Face”and the Prague spring.The “crisis of Marxism”was reflected in Marxism’s objectivistic self-understanding as “scientific socialism,”an approach that downplayed subjectivity and thus seemed to negate human freedom, as the regimes governed by orthodox Marxismdid in actual practice.Husserl’s notion of intentionality offered a compelling alternative to the prevailing scientism, and it was this aspect that was embraced by the phenomenological Marxists in their search for a philosophical orientation that could counter the reigning methodological dogmatism.Insofar as Husserl’s concept of intentionality identified the constitutive function of the transcendental ego as a sine qua non for experience and cognition, it represented a thoroughgoing challenge to all variants of positivism.These preoccupations are central to Husserl’slatework on theCrisis

      of

      the

      European

      Sciences, in which he identifies the “mathemati-cization of nature”as the main culprit.As Husserl observes:“The exclusiveness with which the total worldview of modern man, in the second half of the nineteenth century, let itself be determined by the positive sciences and be blinded by the ‘prosperity’they produced, meant an indifferent turning-away form the questions which are decisive for a genuine humanity.Merely fact-minded sciences make merely fact-minded people.It excludes in principle precisely the questions which man, given over in our unhappy times to the most portentous upheavals, finds the most burning:questions of the meaning or meaninglessness of the whole of this human existence.”(Husserl 6)

    Hermeneutics

    Underlying Habermas’s reception of Dilthey’s work during the 1960s is both a scholarly context as well as a political context.The scholarly context pertains to the revival of debates concerning “explanation

      vs.

      understanding”(?vs)in the human sciences.Whereas the empirical sciences seek to “explain”social phenomena and historical events by subjecting them to causal-nomological accounts, theGeisteswissenschaften, conversely seek tointerpretthem via the non-objectivating technique of understanding (Verstehen).Qua method, understanding seeks, above all, to heed the motivations and intentions of historical actors.In Dilthey’s rendition ofVerstehen, the technique of “empathy”orEinfühlenwas also paramount.This procedure suggested that it was necessary for the historian or interpreter to intuit or identify with the mind set of the actors whose motivations she was trying to comprehend.As a philosopher of culture Dilthey was also the foremost generational representative of-, displaying all of the quirks and limitations of that perspective.Foremost among these limitations was’rather

      frank

      devaluation

      of

      ratiocination

      and

      conceptualization.Bluntly put,intellection, in all its guises and manifestations,constituted

      a

      falsification

      of

      the

      vibrant

      immediacy

      of“life.”As a philosopher of cognition (Erkenntnistheoretiker), Dilthey viewed it as his task to “detranscendentalize”the transcendental subject, orego

      cogito, that had been epistemologically venerated by Descartes and Kant.He vigorously contested the transcendental ego’smaterial

      impoverishment, which he interpreted as a denigration of,or“lived

      experience,”a condition that he associated with the acuteexperiential

      vacuity

      of

      a

      hyper-rationalized,Western

      .As Dilthey remarks in seminal passage fromEinfuhrung

      in

      die

      Geistewissen-schaften:“No

      real

      blood

      flows

      in

      the

      veins

      of

      the

      knowing

      subject

      constructed

      by

      Locke,Hume,and

      Kant;it

      is

      only

      the

      diluted

      juice

      of

      reason,a

      mere

      process

      of

      thought.”(Dilthey 162)Dilthey viewed the very act ofcognitive

      apprehension,or“science,”as

      a

      betrayal

      of“life”().Yet how could one in good conscience aspire to “science”or “knowledge,”if all theory were, as Dilthey claimed, intrinsically an act of betrayal or falsification? In his critique of historical reason Dilthey sought to formulate objective concepts that would make historical life intelligible.Yet isn’t this very act ofsubsuming

      the

      singularity

      of

      lived

      experienceunder the general concepts of “life,”“expression,”and“experience”itself a violation and, as such, objectionable.Even if historicism’s claims about the epistemological superiority of “life”over “ratiocination”were true, from a normative perspec-tive, we would nevertheless remain perplexed:awash

      in

      the

      flux

      of

      experience,and

      thus

      lacking

      a

      fixed

      and

      reliable

      point

      of

      orientation

      to

      guide

      us(Schn?delbach 145).Behind such attitudes and contentions it was not difficult to discern the distinctive echoes of vintageGerman-i.e., theanti-Western,anti-civilizationalethosthat would rise to fever pitch during the 1920s with the work of Spengler, Arthur Moeller van den Bruck, and Martin Heidegger.Like other representatives of German historicism Dilthey was a cultural relativist.Late in life, he elaborated his doctrine of-orworldviews:the

      mental

      parameters

      that

      defined

      a

      given

      period

      or

      epoch.According to this perspective, “values”were intrinsically arbitrary and could never be objectively grounded or justified.For Habermas, Dilthey’s hermeneutics represented what one might call a usable past.By emphasizing the specificity and irreducibility ofVerstehen, Dilthey’s hermeneutics could be enlisted in the methodological and political struggle against the depradations of modern scientism, which had sought to extend its instrumental attitude toward physical nature to the domain of human social action.According to Habermas, “Whereas

      the

      empirical-analytical

      methods

      aim

      at

      disclosing

      and

      comprehending

      under

      the

      transcendental

      viewpoint

      of

      technical

      control,hermeneutic

      methods

      aim

      at

      mutual

      understanding

      in

      ordinary

      language

      communication

      and

      in

      action

      according

      to

      common

      norms.”(Schn?del-bach 176)Surprisingly, the “ideological”objections that the Critical Theory tradition had frequently raised about Dilthey’s work-reservations that had vigorously called into question the “conventionalism,”or over-identification with tradition, as well as thevalue-relativismof the hermeneutic approach-were absent in Habermas’s account.Instead, his criticism of Dilthey paralleled his critique of the other intellectual protagonists discussed inKnowledge

      and

      Human

      Interest:Marx, Peirce, and Freud.Habermas suggested that, like these other thinkers, Dilthey’s approach had succumbed to a “scientistic self-misunderstanding.”Thus despite his penetrating insights concerning the methodological limitations of the natural sciences, Dilthey ultimately succumbed to the predominant illusions of his epoch and sought to legitimate the practice of hermeneutics in the language of scientific objectivity.Paradoxically, he suggested that hermeneutics’claim to methodological superiority was due to the fact that, in the realm of the human sciences, its results could guarantee a greater measure of “objectivity”than could the competing, “naturalizing”approaches that were borrowed from the domain of theNaturwissens-chaften.Habermas refers to this peculiar methodolo-gical blind spot as Dilthey’s “covert positivism”(Schn?delbach 179).InTruth

      and

      Method, Gadamer went far toward redressing one of the major drawbacks of Dilthey’s hermeneutics:its methodological objectivism or latent positivism.Gadamer countered Dilthey’sscien-tistic self-misunderstanding by rejecting the methodological ideal of finality or completion-the Rankean notion that one should interpret historical events “as they really were,”through the eyes of the actors-in favor of a more open-ended, dialogical and hermeneutically situated model of understanding.Yet as Habermas shows, in deftly avoiding one set of methodological failings, Gadamer proceeded to open himself up to another series of complications and compromises.Habermas took exception to the arch-conservative implications of Gadamerian hermeneu-tics, viewing itsglorification

      of

      tradition

      as

      unacceptable, insofar as,historically,traditions

      concealed

      relations

      of

      domination

      that

      were

      inconsistent

      with

      the(Kantian)precepts

      of

      autonomy

      and

      self-determination.Playing Kant to Gadamer’s Burke, he insisted on the ineliminable prerogatives of “reflection”(Reflexion):thusthe

      principles

      of

      democratic

      citizenship

      mandated

      that

      only

      those

      traditions

      were

      acceptable

      that

      could

      be

      explicitly

      and

      rationally

      agreed

      to

      by

      those

      who

      were

      subject

      to

      its

      dictates

      and

      decrees.Thus Gadamer’s unabashed “prejudice

      in

      favor

      of

      prejudice”was flatly irreconcilable with the values of social emancipation.In Habermas’s view, Gadamer’s inflexible defense of tradition (Uberlieferung)was ultimately reminiscent of the discredited worldview of the GermanObrigkeitsstaat(authoritarian state)—a mentality that was conducive to the cultivation of “subjects”(Untertane)rather than “citizens”(ü)who possessed the capacity for self-rule.As Habermas points out, “understanding”(Verstehen)worthy of the name does not mean blindly surrendering to the authority of tradition, but always entails its critical appropriation.When

      all

      is

      said

      and

      done,Gadamer’s

      glorification

      of

      prejudice

      and

      tradition

      demonstrates

      that

      he

      values

      authority

      over

      reason,preservation

      of

      the

      status

      quo

      over

      the

      ideal

      of

      political

      self-determination.Thus whether one chooses Dilthey, Gadamer, or Heidegger, one sees that the hermeneutic tradition suffers certain as.This aversion to universal reason was one of the legacies of the German intellectual-Germany’s self-understanding as aKulturnationin opposition to the purportedly superficial practices ofr?sonnierenthat predominated in the West.Many aspects of the hermeneutic approach were geopolitically conditioned and betrayed what one might callan

      anti-civilizational

      affect—a

      disposition

      that

      surfaced,above

      all,in

      the

      valorization

      of“life”(Leben)over“reason.”As a philosopher, Habermas under-took to cure German political culture of these longstanding prejudices-intellectual habitudes that had had such a deleterious impact on the nation’s moral and political development.With these considerations in mind, it is not surprising to find that, when inTheory

      of

      Communicative

      Action(1981), Habermas reconceived the theoretical framework he had originally developed inKnowledge

      and

      Human

      Interests,the

      references

      to

      hermeneutics

      disap-pear

      almost

      entirely.Instead, in a momentous conceptual shift, he relies on the tradition ofsocial

      phenomenologyas developed by the late Husserl inThe

      Crisisand by Alfred Schütz and Thomas Luckm-ann inStructures

      of

      the

      Lifeworld.In retrospect, this change in perspective seems entirely plausible, since Habermas’s social theoretic reformulation of the critique of instrumental reason parallels Husserl’s interrogation of the worldview of modern science in theCrisis.InTheory

      of

      Communicative

      ActionHabermas reconceptualizes his earlier critique of thetechnological“scientization

      of

      politics”in

      terms

      of

      the

      theme

      of

      the“colonization

      of

      the

      lifeworld.”In the view of most commentators, Husserl’sCrisis, represented a radical new departure.As Paul Ricoeur enquired in his study of Husserl:“How can a philosophy of the cogito, of the radical return to the ego as the founder of all being, become capable of a philosophy of history?”(Ricoeur 145)Conversely, in the eyes of Maurice Merleau-Ponty, theCrisisrepresented a genuine breakthrough, since by abandoning the program of eidetic phenomenology or the search for timeless essences, Husserl had succeeded in exposing phenomenology to new possibilities and horizons.Of course, in theCrisis, although one can unquestionably sense the political tumult of the 1930s hovering in the background, Husserl was only indirectly concerned with real history.Instead, his main focus is on themeaningof history when viewed “eidetically.”His concern was that, in an essential sense, the West had lost its way-by which he meant the telos that had been established during the halcyon days of the Greek Enlightenment.The

      idea

      that

      or

      reason

      should

      govern

      the

      world—as

      opposed

      to

      myth,fate,or

      brute

      force—was

      a

      Greek

      innovation

      that

      had

      been

      codified

      by

      the

      Socratic

      School.Yet, since the late nineteenth century, there could be no denying the fact thatthe

      West’s

      trust

      in

      reason

      had

      been

      tarnished.In its wake, to quote Max Weber, a set of “warring

      gods”had arisen,which

      sought

      to

      supplant

      the

      virtues

      of

      intellection

      with

      irrational

      appeals

      to

      the

      forces

      of“blood”and“race.”Under the circumstances, Husserl, who previously had paid scant attention to moral philosophy, was compelled to undertake a general, metahistorical enquiry concerningthe

      fate

      of

      reason.Yet the real conceptual innovation offered by this rich and fascinating text pertains to Husserl’s development of the idea of the “lifeworld”(Lebenswelt), a bedrock of implicit meanings or taken-for-granted normative assumptions and practices that underlie more formalized domains of social interaction.The lifeworld is the indispensable horizon and basis of human experience.As such, it possesses an existential primacy in light of which all other spheres of life appear as secondary elaborations or constructions.As Husserl explains:“the

      life-world

      ...

      is

      pregiven

      to

      us,the

      waking,practically

      interested

      subjects,always

      and

      necessarily,as

      the

      universal

      field

      of

      all

      actual

      and

      possible

      praxis,as

      horizon.”(Ricoeur 142)

      The lifeworld is the realm of original self-evidences ...All conceivable verification leads back to these modes of self-evidence ...lies in these intuitions themselves as that which is actually, intersubjectively experienceable and verifiable; it is not a subtruction of thought; whereas such a substruction, insofar as it makes a claim to truth, can have actual truth only by being related back to such self-evidences.(Rico-eur 127-28)As individuals, there are two basic attitudes we can assume toward the self-evidences of the lifeworld:a

      na?ve

      attitude

      and

      one

      that

      is

      reflective.It is the latter that Husserl associateswith

      the

      philosophical

      point

      of

      viewand which, for this reason, he judges to be superior.The na?ve attitude declines to go beyond the lifeworld in its immediate givenness.It remains immersed in these experiences and rests content with its immersion.Conversely,the

      reflective

      attitude

      represents

      what

      one

      might

      call

      the

      beginning

      of

      wisdom.Rather than accepting the lifeworld as given, it systematically enquires into the “how”of the lifeworld, its fundamental modalities of givenness.Husserl aptly describes this approach as a “transfor-mation

      of

      the

      thematic

      consciousness

      of

      the

      world

      that

      breaks

      through

      the

      normality

      of

      straightforward

      living.”(Ricoeur 144)Subsequently,what

      was

      once

      self-evident

      and

      unproblematic

      cease

      to

      be

      so.The reflective approach is the fruit of what Husserl refers to in theCrisisas thetranscendental

      epochē:a standpoint that permits the phenomenologist to break with the familiarity of the natural attitude.For

      a

      philosophical

      analogy,one

      might

      have

      recourse

      to

      the

      celebrated“cave

      allegory”in

      Plato’s,in

      which

      one

      prisoner

      breaks

      free

      from

      his

      chains

      in

      order

      to

      perceive

      the

      shadow-play

      that

      his

      fellow

      prisoners

      take

      for

      reality

      or

      the

      truth.

      From

      a

      Hegelian

      perspective,the

      reflective

      attitude

      expresses

      the

      transition

      from

      consciousness

      to

      self-consciousness.It serves as a metaphor for theconversion

      experience

      that

      distinguishes

      the

      philosophical

      point

      of

      view

      from

      common

      sense

      perspective

      of

      the

      everyday

      life.

      The

      epochēaffords

      access

      to

      what

      Husserl

      describes

      as

      the“miracle”of

      transcendental

      subjectivity:the realization that the world does not exist as a self-subsistent entity, as na?ve consciousness might assume.Instead, its being is dependent on the constitutive function of intentional consciousness.Thus,following

      the

      precedents

      of

      Descartes

      and

      Kant,Husserl

      alleges

      that

      the

      world

      never

      appears

      as

      such.

      Instead

      our

      interaction

      with

      it

      is

      conditioned

      a

      priori

      by

      the

      transcendental

      and

      constitutive

      modalities

      of

      intentionality.Here, the concept of intentionality is pivotal insofar as it suggests epistemological limits to the third-person, observer perspective favored by both the natural sciences as well as the positivistically biased social sciences (Geisteswissenschften).In other words:the world-and the socio-cultural world, in particular-cannot be objectively reduced to the “totality of (self-subsistent)facts”if such “facts”are ultimately dependent on the intentionality of consci-ousness.InTheory

      of

      Communicative

      Actionthe lifeworld stands as a realm of informal social meanings and unproblematical cultural assumptions which social actors are able to draw upon freely in order to arrive at shared understandings and to realize their individual and collective projects.Habermas’s normative concerns parallel Husserl’s insofar as both philosophers seek to parry the risks and temptations ofscientific

      overreach:an ever-escalating process whereby more and more aspects of human social life forfeit their autonomy as well as their existential integrity at the hands of highly formalized organiza-tional systems.In the discourse of classical sociology such developments were a central topos.In his pathbreaking studies onSuicideand theDivision

      of

      Labor, Durkheim addressed it under the rubric of thetransition

      from

      mechanical

      to

      organic

      solidarity.

      In a number of key works, Max Weber harbored similar fears and concerns.He famously concludedThe

      Protestant

      Ethic

      and

      the

      Spirit

      of

      Capitalismby denigrating the ethos of the modernFachmenschor specialist as a cultural setback when considered against the backdrop of the Renaissance ideal of the well-rounded personality.His critique of thefateful

      one-sidedness

      of

      modern

      cultural

      development—the

      triumph

      of“objective”over“subjective”culture-led him to formulate his conception of modernityas

      a

      process

      of

      twofold“loss”:a “loss of meaning”and a “loss of freedom”(und).“Loss

      of

      meaning”derives from the process of rationalization, whereby the mores and convictions of traditional society areincreasingly

      subjected

      to

      the

      corrosive

      force

      of

      intellectualist

      criteria

      as

      well

      as

      the

      universal

      solvent

      of

      scientific

      reason.“Loss

      of

      freedom”results from the universaltriumph

      of

      bureaucracyas a seemingly inescapable mode of social organization.Thus increasinglyfewer

      spheres

      of

      life

      are

      able

      to

      escape

      the

      straightjacket

      of

      formal

      reason.Bureaucracy’s rise means thatincreasingly

      fewer

      aspects

      of

      social

      and

      vocational

      life

      are

      left

      to

      individual

      inclination,whim,initiative,or

      choice.Instead, nearly all aspects of social life areregulated

      and

      predetermined-down to the innermost “corpuscu-lar”level, as Michel Foucault observes with reference to the growth of “biopower”in the modern world.Reliance on the lifeworld concept allows Habermas to analyze such developments in ways thatthe

      hermeneutic

      approach—with

      its

      shortsighted

      and

      limited

      glorification

      of

      the

      ineffable

      immediacy

      of“life”-did not.Thereby, he can indict the improper overreach of “functionalist

      reason”:the illicit interferences of rational-purposive approaches to social action (zweckra-tionalesHandeln)in areas of society that are rooted in the lifeworld:thefamily,culture,community

      life,and

      voluntary

      associations, whose informal modalities are increasingly subjected to the formal media of money and power.Habermas

      develops

      the

      idea

      of

      the“colonization

      of

      the

      lifeworld”to

      highlight

      the

      illegitimate

      and

      destructive

      violations

      of

      the

      lifeworld’s

      integrity

      by

      the

      forces

      of

      instrumental

      rationality

      deriving

      from

      the

      subsystems

      of

      the

      economy

      and

      state

      administration.Nevertheless, there are shortcomings to the lifeworld approach, as developed by social phenomenologists like Husserl and Schutz, which, inTheory

      of

      Communicative

      Action, Habermas seeks to surmount.Despite the pluralistic implications of the lifeworld concept, phenomenology remains wedded to the perspective of transcendental subjectivity, which perceives the world from the standpoint of individually thinking and acting subjects.Hence, phenomenology’s well known difficulties when it comes to the problem of “other minds”or intersubjectivity.Habermas wishes to circumvent these obstacles by reformulating the lifeworld idea in keeping with the tenets ofcommunicative

      reason, for whichintersubjectivityremains a touchstone.But also, from the phenomenological standpoint, reason and rationality remain extraneous concerns; they have no place in discussions of the lifeworld, where implicit knowledge, rather than rationality, predominates.Via hiscommunicative

      reformulation

      of

      the

      lifeworld

      ideal, Habermas is able to introduce into the discussion a normative dimension that in phenomenological approaches—with

      their

      predo-minant

      orientation

      toward

      rather

      than-typically remains absent.As

      a

      norm,communicative

      reason

      suggests

      that

      the

      denizens

      of

      the

      lifeworld

      dispose

      over

      specific

      criteria

      of

      reasonableness

      and

      fairness

      that

      may

      be

      invoked

      to

      adjudicate

      the

      validity

      of

      the

      agreements

      and

      understandings

      they

      reach.Thus whereas the notion of the lifeworld, as a constant feature of human societies, is, strictly speaking, transhistorical,with

      the

      transition

      from

      commun-ity

      to

      society,its“rationality

      potentials”expand—as

      do

      its

      potentials

      for

      justice

      as

      fairness.One of the keys to Habermas’s argument revolves around a process that he denominates the “linguistification

      of

      the

      sacred.”Among traditi-onal societies in which religion remains a primary mode of securing legitimation,the

      aura

      of

      the

      sacred

      serves

      to

      immunize

      social

      authority

      from

      discursive

      challenges, which undercuts the communicative ideal of understanding oriented toward mutual agreement.Conversely, with the advent of secularization, these ideological barriers dwindle.Illegitimate

      claims

      to

      social

      authority

      are

      deprived

      of

      the

      patina

      of

      divinity

      behind

      which

      they

      have

      been

      traditionally

      able

      to

      dissemble

      their

      normative

      and

      political

      gist.

      In

      their

      place

      there

      emerges

      a

      new

      potential

      for

      a

      non-hierarchical,consensual

      resolution

      of

      disputes,along

      with

      egalitarian

      prospects

      of

      democratic

      will-formation.Habermas formulates these issues in a key passage inTheory

      of

      Commun-icative

      Action, volume II:Universal discourse points to an idealized lifeworld reproduced through processes of mutual understanding that have been largely detached from normative contexts and transferred over to rationally motivated yes/no positions.This sort of growing autonomy can come to pass only to the extent thatconstraints

      of

      material

      reproduction

      no

      longer

      hide

      behind

      the

      mask

      of

      a

      rationally

      impenetrable,basic,normative

      consensus,that

      is,stand

      behind

      the

      authority

      of

      the

      sacred[...] A lifeworld rationalized in this sense would by no means reproduce itself in conflict-free forms.But the conflicts would appear in their own names; they would no longer be concealed by convictions immune from discursive examination.(145)By the same token, ultimately, the lifeworld approach shares one of the central methodological shortcomings of its hermeneutic cousin, a failing that we have already discussed under the rubric of “hermeneutic idealism.”This appellation suggests that the model of intentionality and implicit meanings offers inadequate means for conceptualizing problems of power and domination.What is also needed is an analysis of “system integration”that complements the emphasis on symbolic meanings that derive from the phenomenological approach.Systems theory’s methodological point of departure is not the intentionality of the individual social actor or actors.Instead, it adopts the functionalist perspective of the self-maintaining system that it inherits from nineteenth-century social evolutionism.Its socio-political ideal is “homeostasis,”a normative standpoint that it borrows from the life sciences-above all, biology.Habermas’s project of a “critique of functionalist reason”aims to roll back or curtail the illicit interferences of the instrumental imperatives that derive from the self-maintaining systems of economy and power in the lifeworld qua repository of implicit meanings.InTheory

      of

      Communicative

      Action, he describes the reifying or “de-moralizing”effect of system-induced interferences in the lifeworld as follows:A demoralized, positive, compulsory law [...] makes it possible to steer social action via delinguistified media [...] The transfer of action coordination from language over to steering media means an uncoupling of interaction from lifeworld contexts.Media such as money and power [...] encode a purposive-rational attitude toward calculable amounts of value and make it possible to exert generalized, strategic influence [...] whilebypassingprocesses of consensus-oriented communic-ation.[As a result] the lifeworld contexts in which processes of reaching understanding are always embedded are devalued in favor of media-steered interactions.(Theory

      of

      Communicative

      Action154)Thus under conditions of advanced capitalism, domination (Herrschaft)assumes the form of strategic rationality.By virtue of its central role in processes of system maintenance, it acquires an aura of “objectivity”and is thereby substantially immunized against claims of democratic legitimacy.Consequently, thefunctionalimperatives of instrumental reason trump thediscursiveclaims of communicative reason as they are rooted in the lifeworld.The end result of this process is what Habermas callsthe“”(Theory

      of

      Communicative

      Action180,183).By

      substituting

      impersonal

      mechanisms

      of

      strategic

      action

      for

      communicative

      reason,the

      coloniza-tion

      of

      the

      lifeworld

      facilitates

      the

      .This occurs insofar aswe

      associate

      the

      capacity

      for

      moral

      action

      with

      the

      values

      of

      collective

      self-determination

      and

      individual

      autonomy.

      Yet

      individual

      autonomy

      diminishes

      the

      more

      that

      the

      amoral

      steering

      media

      of

      money

      and

      power

      degrade

      the

      discursive

      fabric

      of

      the

      lifeworld

      qua

      fount

      of

      intersubjectivity

      and

      communicative

      rationality.

    Critical Remarks

    One of Habermas’s primary goals inTheory

      of

      Communicative

      Actionis to redress the question of the absent normative foundations of the Frankfurt School.Yet in this regard, there seems to be a fundamental ambivalence at the heart of his approach—an ambivalence that has, in certain respects, persistently haunted Critical Theory.Bluntly put:do these normative foundations possess an immanent or transcendent status? Are they rooted in universal principles or are they, instead, socially embodied.If they are “transcend-ent,”then they risk assuming the character of standards or precepts that have been independently derived and determined by the philosopher or theorist.If, conversely, they are sedimented in the logic of social development, they threaten to become overly concrete:the expression of a particular cultural tradition or a given social formation.As a result, their claim to universality diminishes correspondingly.Habermas, for his part, has shown himself to be extremely uncomfortable with the idea of timeless, unconditional claims to validity as a lapse into foundationalism.Instead, he has on numerous occasions expressed solidarity with trends in “postmetaphysical thinking.”Consequently, his attitude toward the question of ultimate foundations (letzteBegründungen)has persistently oscillated between a transcendental and empirical orientation, as can be seen by his employment of the oxymoron “quasi-transcendental”to characterize his aims.Yet normative claims that are quasi-transcendentalseem

      alternately

      too

      strong

      and

      too

      weak, insofar as they seek the unimpugnability of ultimate foundations without the attendant metaphysical baggage.Yet here, it is unclear exactly what role the lifeworld, as a realm of informal and taken-for-granted habitudes and meanings, is meant to play in validatingthe

      normative

      telos

      of

      communicative

      reason:uncoerced

      reciprocal

      agreement,mutual

      understanding

      free

      from

      ideological

      constraints

      or

      distortion.As a diffuse congeries of values, significations, and background conditions,there

      is

      nothing

      inherently“rational”about

      the

      life-world.Instead, one can readily imagine that the lifeworld’s suitability for the ends of communicative transparency would change radically depending on the extent to which it has been institutionally “rationalized,”or exposed to the mechanisms andnorms

      of

      democratic

      publicity(?ffentlichkeit)—a point that Habermas generally seems willing to concede.Thus one can readily conceive of lifeworlds that function in ways that are extremely arbitrary or repressive; lifeworlds in which the distortional effects of tradition prevent the norms of equality and reciprocity that Habermas reveres from flourishing.In sum, ultimately, one must judge the fabric of a given lifeworld on the basis of its normative content,since

      lifeworlds

      that

      are

      obstinately

      mired

      in

      custom,habit,and

      tradition

      can

      easily

      present

      themselves

      as

      obstacles

      to,rather

      than

      facilitators

      of,the

      ends

      of

      social

      emancipation.

      Thus

      lifeworlds

      can

      be“ethical,”or

      cohere

      internally,without

      being“moral”—that

      is,without

      adhering

      to

      broader

      norms

      of

      justice

      or

      fairness.

      Given such questions and doubts, one cannot help but wonder whether Habermas places more methodological weight on the lifeworld ideal than it can in point of fact bear.Thus in view of the historical variegatedness of individual lifeworlds, how reliable is this concept as a basis or ground for a theory of communicative reason?In a subsequent clarification, Habermas seems to concede too much to thelifeworld

      qua“ethical

      life”or—that

      is,as

      a

      sphere

      of

      random, “amoral”sociality—when he claims that attempts to pose questions of “ultimate

      justification”(letzteBegründungen)with respect to the lifeworld arefundamentally

      misplaced.“The

      intuitions

      of

      everyday

      life,”he

      avows, “have

      no

      need

      of

      clarification

      by

      philosophers.”Instead, “in

      this

      case,the

      understanding

      of

      philosophy

      as

      developed

      by

      Wittgenstein

      seems

      appropriate.”(Moral

      Cons-ciousness98)In other words:when it comes to the lifeworld, philosophy should not disturb the fragile heritage of tradition, even if that heritage should turn out to be a dead weight.Instead, following Wittgenstein,philosophy’s

      job

      is

      merely

      to

      clarify

      the

      nature

      of

      life

      practices

      and

      the

      rules

      that

      underlie

      them,rather

      than

      to

      disrupt

      the

      lifeworld’s

      integrity

      by

      seeking

      to

      impose

      first

      principles

      or

      to

      legislate

      norms.Yet in the preceding characterization,the

      lifeworld

      seems

      to

      be

      synonymous

      with

      a

      approach

      to

      life,one

      that

      assumes

      that

      the

      totality

      of

      inherited

      social

      facts

      is

      fundamentally

      unalterable.

      A-approach

      to

      life,conversely,suggests

      the

      advent

      of“critical

      consciousness”:a

      consciousness

      that

      no

      longer

      merely

      assumes

      that

      the

      contents

      of

      tradition

      merit

      acceptance

      merely

      because

      they

      have

      been

      handed

      down.Hence, it seems that, in opposition to the conventionalist approach, one must adopt a principle akin to Jaspers’notion of the “axial age,”a concept that denotes theadvent

      of“transcendence”as

      a

      precondition

      for

      critical

      consciousness.As Jaspers proposes inThe

      Origin

      and

      Goal

      of

      History(1949), “transcendence”signifies

      a

      capacity

      for

      that

      transcends

      the

      world

      as

      a

      self-referential

      totality

      of

      facts.Here, it connotes the emergence of acapacity

      to

      judge

      the

      normative

      failings

      and

      deficiencies

      of“ethical

      life”()according

      to

      considerations

      of:according

      to

      the

      higher

      moral

      standards

      of“justice.”Habermas has invoked the idea of the axial age in his later writings on the philosophy of religion; although he has not indicated what role it might play a role in reformulating the idea of the lifeworld he develops inTheory

      of

      Communicative

      Action.Notes① Dilthey,Introduction

      to

      the

      Human

      Sciences(Princeton:Princeton University Press, 1989); 1uoted in Dilthey,Selected

      Writings, ed.H.Rickman (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1976), 162.See also, Georg Iggers,The

      German

      Conception

      of

      History:the

      National

      Tradition

      of

      Historical

      Thought

      from

      Herder

      to

      the

      Present(Wesleyan University Press:1983).② “For Husserl, objectivity was always a particular ‘achievement of consciousness’(Bewussteinsleistung)and he was fascinated by the miracle of the process.”See Dermot Moran.Introduction

      to

      Phenomenology(New York:Routledge, 2000).60.③ See Jaspers,The

      Origin

      and

      Goal

      of

      History(New York:Routledge, 2016).Works CitedHabermas, Jürgen.Moral

      Consciousness

      and

      Communicative

      Action.Cambridge, Mass.:MIT Press, 1992.- - -.Theory

      of

      Communicative

      ActionII.Trans.T.McCarthy.Boston:Beacon Press, 1987.- - -.Theory

      and

      Practice.Trans.J.Viertel.Boston:Beacon Press, 1973.Husserl, Edmund.The

      Crisis

      of

      the

      European

      Sciences

      and

      Transcendental

      Phenomenology.Trans.D.Carr.Evanston:Northwestern University Press, 1970.Schn?delbach.Philosophy

      in

      Germany:1831-1933.New York:Cambridge University Press, 1984.Ricoeur, Paul.Husserl:An

      Analysis

      of

      His

      Phenomenology.Trans.E.Ballard and L.Embree.Evanston:Northwestern University Press, 1967.

      本文标题:Habermas and Hermeneutics:From Verstehen to Lebenswelt

      本文链接:https://www.99guiyi.com/content/678910.html

      • 评论
      0条评论
      • 最新评论

      深度阅读

      • 您也可以注册成为归一的作者,发表您的原创作品、分享您的心情!